argument types
on this page
overview
arguments are structured collections of statements where premises provide support for a conclusion. the type of argument determines how strongly the premises support the conclusion and what kind of reasoning is involved.
this section covers the four main types of arguments in logical reasoning, each with distinct characteristics and applications in automated reasoning, science, and everyday thinking.
argument types
deductive arguments
premises provide necessary consequence - if premises are true, the conclusion must be true.
all humans are mortal (premise)
socrates is human (premise)
∴ socrates is mortal (conclusion)
characteristics:
- validity: structure guarantees truth preservation
- soundness: valid + all premises actually true
- certainty: conclusions follow necessarily
- monotonic: adding premises cannot invalidate
learn more about deductive arguments →
inductive arguments
premises provide probabilistic support - make conclusion more likely but don’t guarantee it.
the sun has risen every day for 4.6 billion years (premise)
the laws of physics remain constant (premise)
∴ the sun will probably rise tomorrow (conclusion)
characteristics:
- strength: degree of support (weak to strong)
- cogency: strong + premises probably true
- ampliative: conclusion goes beyond premises
- statistical: often based on patterns or frequencies
learn more about inductive arguments →
abductive arguments
premises suggest the best explanation for observed phenomena.
the ground is wet (observation)
if it rained, the ground would be wet (premise)
∴ it probably rained (best explanation)
characteristics:
- inference to best explanation: among competing hypotheses
- explanatory power: accounts for observations
- defeasible: better explanations can defeat conclusions
- creative: generates new hypotheses
learn more about abductive arguments →
defeasible arguments
provide strong support that can be defeated by additional information.
birds typically fly (default rule)
tweety is a bird (premise)
∴ tweety probably flies (conclusion)
can be defeated by learning tweety is a penguin or has a broken wing.
characteristics:
- non-monotonic: new information can invalidate
- presumptive: based on defaults or generalizations
- revisable: conclusions are tentative
- exception-handling: admits counterexamples
learn more about defeasible arguments →
comparison matrix
type | certainty | monotonic | purpose | example domain |
---|---|---|---|---|
deductive | necessary | yes | proof | mathematics |
inductive | probable | yes | generalization | science |
abductive | plausible | no | explanation | diagnosis |
defeasible | presumptive | no | practical reasoning | everyday decisions |
validity vs soundness
understanding the distinction between validity and soundness is crucial for evaluating arguments:
validity (structure)
an argument is valid if the conclusion logically follows from the premises, regardless of whether the premises are actually true.
valid but unsound:
all cats are purple (false premise)
fluffy is a cat (true premise)
∴ fluffy is purple (false conclusion, but validly derived)
soundness (structure + truth)
an argument is sound if it is both valid AND all premises are actually true.
sound argument:
all mammals are warm-blooded (true premise)
whales are mammals (true premise)
∴ whales are warm-blooded (true conclusion)
only deductive arguments can be sound. inductive and abductive arguments are evaluated differently:
- inductive: strong/weak + cogent/uncogent
- abductive: plausible/implausible based on explanatory power
- defeasible: reasonable/unreasonable given current information
strength measures
different argument types use different evaluation criteria:
deductive arguments
- validity: all or nothing (valid or invalid)
- soundness: requires both validity and true premises
inductive arguments
- strength: continuous scale from weak to strong
- cogency: strong + probably true premises
- probability: can assign numerical confidence values
abductive arguments
- plausibility: relative to competing explanations
- explanatory virtues: simplicity, scope, fit with background knowledge
- likelihood:
defeasible arguments
- reasonableness: given current information
- defeat conditions: what evidence would overturn the conclusion
- strength: how much additional evidence needed for defeat
practical applications
automated reasoning
- theorem provers: deductive arguments for formal verification
- machine learning: inductive arguments from data to models
- diagnostic systems: abductive arguments for best explanations
- expert systems: defeasible rules with exception handling
scientific reasoning
- mathematical proofs: deductive arguments
- hypothesis testing: inductive arguments from samples
- theory formation: abductive arguments explaining phenomena
- model revision: defeasible arguments updated by new evidence
everyday reasoning
- formal logic: deductive arguments in structured domains
- pattern recognition: inductive arguments from experience
- troubleshooting: abductive arguments for problem causes
- practical decisions: defeasible arguments with exceptions
legal reasoning
- statutory interpretation: deductive application of rules
- precedent analysis: inductive reasoning from case patterns
- fact finding: abductive reasoning about what happened
- burden of proof: defeasible presumptions and rebuttals
common confusions
argument vs explanation
- argument: premises support conclusion (evidence → claim)
- explanation: describes why something is true (cause → effect)
argument: "it's raining, so the ground will be wet"
explanation: "the ground is wet because it's raining"
correlation vs causation
- correlation: statistical association between variables
- causation: one variable actually causes changes in another
inductive arguments from correlation to causation are often weak without additional evidence.
necessary vs sufficient conditions
- necessary: must be present for conclusion (if not A, then not B)
- sufficient: enough by itself for conclusion (if A, then B)
confusion about these leads to fallacies like affirming the consequent.
implementation notes
when building reasoning systems:
deductive systems
- use formal logic (propositional, predicate)
- implement inference rules (modus ponens, etc.)
- ensure soundness and completeness
- handle computational complexity
inductive systems
- collect sufficient sample sizes
- handle biased data appropriately
- compute confidence intervals
- account for multiple inductive biases
abductive systems
- generate multiple hypotheses
- rank by explanatory power
- update as new evidence arrives
- balance simplicity vs accuracy
defeasible systems
- represent default rules with exceptions
- implement defeat mechanisms
- handle rule conflicts
- maintain consistency during updates
further reading
foundational texts
- aristotle’s “prior analytics” (deductive logic)
- hume’s “enquiry concerning human understanding” (inductive reasoning)
- peirce’s collected papers (abductive reasoning)
- reiter’s “default logic” (defeasible reasoning)
modern treatments
- bergmann, moor & nelson: “the logic book”
- salmon: “logic”
- josephson & josephson: “abductive inference”
- brewka, dix & konolige: “nonmonotonic reasoning”
computational approaches
- russell & norvig: “artificial intelligence: a modern approach”
- pearl: “probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems”
- pollock: “cognitive carpentry”
- prakken & vreeswijk: “logics for defeasible argumentation”
══════════════════════════════════════════════════════════════════